Marginalizing
the Maker:
The Status of Authorship in the Digital Epoch
by A. D. Coleman
Will copyright
become irrelevant in the electronic age?
Provoked by a
polemic penned by the late critic and photographer
Derek Bennett, I began considering this question in
our last issue by examining the function of copyright
in the economic life of those whose work involves
embodying ideas and information in physical forms.
I concluded by indicating that there was another way
in which copyright empowered those writers, photographers,
artists and others among us engaged in such labors.
In his germinal
essay, "Author as Producer," the German
critic Walter Benjamin makes it clear that, as a worker,
I have an ongoing, vested interest -- not only economic
but also political, and moral -- in the material I
generate as a writer. He argues that my job doesn't
end with the final draft, but only begins there; in
his view, it's incumbent upon me to exercise whatever
control I can so as to ensure that, in the way it's
edited and published, my work truly ends up serving
my original purposes, furthering my commitments and
goals rather than those beliefs to which I'm opposed.(1)
If I agree with
Benjamin, and I do, how can I achieve such control
over my work? After all, prior to publication, it
passes through various editorial hands, in a process
via which it could be subject to all kinds of alterations.
Then, once off the press, my ideas are there on the
printed page for any reader to absorb, reject, expand
upon, revise; I can't (and wouldn't want to) dictate
or overdetermine my readers' responses. By publishing,
therefore, I've given those ideas to the world.
My texts, however,
are not freely available for anyone's commercial or
non-commercial use, because they are copyrighted.
Significantly, this not only protects my legitimate,
continuing economic relation to my own work but also
safeguards that work against unauthorized alteration
and undesired recontextualization -- that is, against
misuses for which I cannot and should not be held
responsible -- both prior to publication and thereafter.
By extension,
that reasoning applies to everyone who generates ideas
embodied in tangible form -- including artists and
photographers. It was on that basis that Federal District
Court Judge Charles S. Haight recently ruled in favor
of professional photographer Art Rogers, who'd sued
the artist Jeff Koons for exhibiting and selling "String
of Puppies," a sculptural, polychromed-wood version
of Rogers's black & white photograph titled "Puppies."
The language of Judge Haight's decision is instructive.
He opined that "Koons's sculpture does not criticize
or comment upon Rogers's photograph. It simply appropriates
it." (Koons had claimed that his use of the Rogers
image had constituted fair use, examples of which
would include criticism of or comment upon another
work.) Having thus raised a specter to haunt every
Madison Avenue art director with a MacIntosh as well
as every postmodern appropriationist in SoHo, the
judge found for the plaintiff because the Copyright
Act "confers upon the copyright owner the exclusive
rights to do and authorize . . . 'the preparation
of derivative works.'"(2)
This enlightened
defense of the autonomy of photographers is precedent-setting
here; undoubtedly it will undergo further challenge,
testing and refinement in the courts. The French have
already institutionalized a similarly expanded understanding
of copyright in two farsighted laws. One of these
is called the droit de suite, which translates roughly
as "follow-up rights"; it guarantees artists
a share in the future profits from all subsequent
resales of their work. (California has adopted a version
of this law, which mandates the payment of "resale
royalties" to artists and photographers; similar
laws are now under discussion in other states. How
this will apply to the rapidly spreading practice
of using scanned and digitized photos in desktop publishing
and computer graphics is of course a particularly
thorny question.)
The second of
these pioneering French laws is called the droit morale,
or "moral right"; it ensures that artists'
works must always be properly attributed to them and
cannot be altered without their consent after they
are sold. (European photojournalists are now demanding
a variant of this rule that's specific to their profession;
they're calling it the droit de regard, and it boils
down to the kind of input into the editorial process
for which W. Eugene Smith fought all his life.(3))
Versions of this
model law have been passed, or are under consideration,
in many countries now, including the United States,
where Robert Rauschenberg, among others, has championed
it. (Rather ironic, in light of Rauschenberg's "appropriation"
of many images in his early silk-screen paintings.)
Late last year, after six years' debate, Congress
amended the Copyright Act by enacting the Visual Artists'
Rights Act (VARA), which grants to some visual artists
what a lawyer specializing in the arts -- Barbara
Hoffmann, Honorary Counsel to the College Art Association
-- calls "limited rights of attribution and integrity."
(VARA applies only to paintings, drawings, prints,
and sculptures that exist either in unique versions
or in limited editions of up to 200 examples, which
must be consecutively numbered and signed.)(4)
Such legislation
cannot logically be supported without recognizing
the clear parallels between it and the necessary assurances
that copyright offers to writers; after all, that's
why it's an amendment to the Copyright Act. To argue
against copyright, therefore, is to dismiss out of
hand the essential protection for artists and photographers
that is represented by the droit morale and the droit
de suite.
If everyone is
free to do whatever they feel like with anyone else's
work -- re-edit it, change a line of reasoning or
an aspect of style, alter its form, put words (or
images) into its maker's mouth, publish or present
it in contexts they find abhorrent -- then surely
any responsible maker of work will feel entitled,
even obligated, to disclaim any such version of it
as unauthorized, especially if it bears his or her
name and thereby carries whatever credibility has
accrued to them by reputation. Even with a strong
copyright law, such abuses abound; tracking them and
ensuring the publication of such disavowals is already
not only undependable and after the fact of any damage
done but also burdensome, tedious, and costly, as
demonstrated by Art Rogers's experience. One doesn't
need much imagination to foresee that, absent the
copyright law, the instances would multiply exponentially
and setting the record straight would become virtually
impossible.
Parenthetically,
I'd add that the elimination of copyright would let
writers, photographers and artists off the hook, too
easily, as perpetrators of political acts (for that
is, among other things, how all verbal and visual
statements made in public forums function). Copyright
serves to keep us honest. It makes it less plausible
and more difficult for us casually to disclaim our
responsibilities to and for our works on the grounds
that they were out of our control, that someone else
operating without permission altered them or used
them in contexts to which we stand opposed.
Fundamentally,
what copyright does -- like a signature on a document
-- is make one personally and professionally liable
for one's actions. In my case, for example, it assures
the reader that I've produced and given my consent
to the statements he or she reads under my by-line,
and have taken responsibility for their consequences;
that I've considered and approved the presentational
vehicle in which it's appearing; that (inasmuch as
possible -- there's always a gremlin) I've authenticated
the integrity of that version of my text; and that
I'm therefore the one who's due the credit and/or
the blame for the life this example of my work leads
in the world.
I insist on those
as the conditions under which I publish; for, in the
last analysis, if I can't be held morally and legally
accountable by my fellow citizens for what I say in
print, the context in which it appears, and the determinable
effects of those choices, what possible weight can
my words carry?
Whatever else
it may bring, if the digital epoch encourages the
diminution of that accountability, I won't consider
it a change for the better. To reiterate what I said
last month, ideas can't be possessed; but they can
and should be properly attributed to those who originated
and embodied them in whatever form is under discussion
at a particular moment, and the integrity of that
form can and should be maintained and respected. In
my opinion, the makers of embodied ideas -- among
whom I include myself -- should not be marginalized,
either legally or conceptually, in their relation
to their works. Quite the opposite: they deserve both
the credit and the blame, the rewards and the punishments,
that are due as a result of the impact their works
have on their world.
Notes:
(1)
Walter Benjamin, "Author as Producer," in
Victor Burgin, ed., Thinking Photography, (London:
The MacMillan Press, Ltd.), pp. 15-31.
(2)
For a thoughtful summary of the Art Rogers v. Jeff
Koons and Sonnabend Gallery, Inc. trial and decision,
and the legal issues underlying same, see Barbara
Hoffman, "Legal Update: Whose Image Is It?"
CAA News, Vol. 15, no. 5 (September-October 1990),
pp. 5-6, and the same author's follow-up story, "Legal
Update: . . . and the Winner Is," CAA News, Vol.
16, no. 3 (May-June 1991), p. 6. Hoffman -- not a
participant in the case -- served at that time as
Honorary Counsel for the College Art Association (C.A.A.).
(3)
For a report on the opening salvo in the battle for
the droit de regard, see my account of the 1989 Rencontres
Internationales de la Photographie, "Letter From:
Arles, No. 6" Photo Metro, Vol. 8, no. 72 (September
1989), pp. 24-25.
(4)
Hoffman, "Legal Update: . . . and the Winner
Is," loc. cit.
This essay first
appeared in Camera & Darkroom Photography,
Vol. 13, no. 11 (November 1991). It subsequently appeared
in my book The Digital Evolution: Visual Communication
in the Electronic Age, Essays, Lectures and Interviews
1967-1998 (Nazraeli Press, 1998; second edition,
Villa Florentine Books, 2002).
back
to top